Absurd Being

A place to take a moment to reflect on what it all means

George Berkeley 1685-1754
Existentialism

Philosophy Categories

Existentialism


Ancient Greece


Stoicism


Medieval


Modern

Berkeley

Recommended Reading



A Treatise Concerning The Principles of Human Knowledge  

Summaries

->  A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge

The Man

George Berkeley was born the eldest of six sons on March 12, 1685 in Ireland, and although his father, William Berkeley, was English, his son always considered himself Irish. In 1696, Berkeley entered Kilkenny College and four years later, Trinity College, Dublin. He graduated with his B.A. in 1704. After becoming a Master in 1707, he was elected a Junior Fellow of Trinity College, becoming a Senior Fellow in 1717, a position he would hold until 1724. He was ordained as a deacon in 1709 and as an Anglican priest in 1710.

During his time at Trinity College, Berkeley published the four works he is best known for; An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision (1709), A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part 1 (1710), Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (1713), and De Motu (1721). In the Essay, Berkeley argued that objects perceived by sight did not exist without the mind. The Treatise expanded this thesis to cover all perceived objects, and can be summed up by the phrase esse est percipi (to be is to be perceived). The Dialogues reinforce the arguments made in the Treatise.

After the publication of his Principles, Berkeley, eager to engage in disputation with critics, inquired of his friend in London, Lord John Percival, “If when you receive my book, you can procure me the opinion of some of your acquaintances who are thinking men… I shall be extremely obliged to you.” Unfortunately, for the twenty-five year old Berkeley, Percival reported back that his work had only managed to excite ridicule.   

After completing his Dialogues, which he no doubt hoped would help to popularise his ideas, Berkeley travelled to London on a leave of absence with Trinity in 1713. While in London, he became friends with some of the leading intellectuals of the time, including Johnathan Swift and Alexander Pope. In 1713-14, he travelled through parts of Europe as chaplain to Lord Peterborough, during which time he met the philosopher Nicholas Malebranche.

From 1716-21, Berkeley obtained another leave of absence to accompany the Bishop of Clogher on his travels in the capacity of tutor to the Bishop’s son. During this period, Berkeley reportedly lost the second part of his Principles, a work he would never manage to reproduce.  

Around 1722, disillusioned by the prevalence of free-thought in England, Berkeley turned his attention towards the “New World” and began planning to build a church in Bermuda, where he hoped to help create a new civilisation founded on Christianity. He lobbied for this and was able to secure a promise of £20,000 from the British Parliament. After marrying Anne Foster in 1728, he and his new wife left for America, settling in Newport, Rhode Island. The couple moved to Whitehall the following year, where they would stay until 1731, at which time the Prime Minister of England admitted the £20,000 would not be forthcoming, and Berkeley was forced to abandon his grand plans. After returning to London, he continued writing. It was at this time that he published Alciphron: or the Minute Philosopher (1732), which was a spirited defence of Christianity against the thoughts of deists and freethinkers.   

Berkeley returned to Dublin in 1734, where he was consecrated Bishop of Cloyne. While in Cloyne, Berkeley had two more sons and two daughters, adding to the two sons he already had. Berkeley remained in Cloyne until his retirement in 1752. He moved to Oxford later that year and died the following year on January 14.


The Timeline

1685: Born on March 12 in or near Kilkenny, Ireland

1696: Enrolled in Kilkenny College

1700: Enrolled in Trinity College, Dublin

1704: Obtained his B.A.

1707: Obtained his Masters

           Elected a Junior Fellow of Trinity College

1709: Published An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision

           Ordained a deacon

1710: Published A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part 1

           Became an Anglican priest

1713: Obtained a leave of absence and travelled to London

           Published Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous

1713-14: Travelled to Europe as chaplain to Lord Peterborough

1716-21: Travelled to Europe again, this time as tutor to the son of the Bishop of Clogher

1717: Became a Senior Fellow of Trinity College

1721: Published De Motu

1728: Married Anne Foster

           Moved to Newport, Rhode Island

1729: Moved to Whitehall

1731: Returned to London

1732: Published Alciphron: or the Minute Philosopher

1734: Moved to Dublin to become Bishop of Cloyne

1752: Retired

1753: Moved to Oxford

1754: Died on January 14

The Philosophy

Bishop George Berkeley is the second of the three British Empiricists. His main work, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part 1, is a concise, very readable argument for idealism and immaterialism. Berkeley’s central philosophical idea is his rejection of the theory of matter; i.e. that there can be a substance which exists independently of a perceiving mind.

 

Abstract Ideas

The Introduction of the Treatise is a sustained criticism of the notion of abstract ideas, which he thinks are responsible for all manner of confused and unclear thinking. Abstract ideas are formed when we take qualities or modes of things and consider them apart from the object in which they are found. Berkeley’s argument is that abstract ideas don’t exist; that is, it is impossible to actually formulate a coherent idea in the mind, of an abstraction. The reason is that the abstract idea is an idea which, by definition, lacks any qualities. The abstract idea of colour, for example, lacks colour, and that of extension is a type of extension “which is neither line, surface, nor solid, nor has any figure or magnitude” (Introduction, sect. 8).

 

Esse est Percipi

The whole of George Berkeley’s philosophy is centred on the phrase, esse est percipi (to be is to be perceived). In the same way that thoughts, passions, and imagined ideas can’t exist without the mind, “to me it seems no less evident that the various sensations, or ideas imprinted on the Sense… cannot exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving them.” (Part First, sect. 3)

This seems outrageous at first glance, but upon closer inspection, may appear less so. There are basically two ways of approaching this idea. In the first, Berkeley simply asks us not to make inferences where we have no solid grounds for doing so. What are bodies, as far as we know? The bodies we perceive are, in truth, nothing more than sensations impressed on our minds. If we really wish to ground our philosophy only on what we know for sure, and resist the temptation to speculate about the way things might be, this is all we reasonably claim. Descartes, for example, upon noting the ideas excited in his mind by his senses, went on to postulate the existence of some form of extended substance (matter) as the cause of these ideas. If he had remained true to his method of doubt, he would have stopped at the ideas and refused to speculate about possible causes.

The second way is to reflect on whether we can really conceive of a body existing without a perceiving mind. Berkeley isn’t asking whether we can simply imagine a body without any perceiving witnesses; rather, he’s asking if the idea of a body without a perceiver is coherent. A body that we perceive is not just a body; it’s a body that we perceive. Bodies never, in actual fact or as far as we know, appear without an observer.      

 

Primary and Secondary Qualities

Berkeley takes up Locke’s distinction between primary and secondary qualities; the former including extension, figure, motion, rest, solidity or impenetrability, and number; the latter, all sensible qualities such as, colour, sound, taste, etc. It is held to be uncontroversial that secondary qualities don’t exist without the mind; i.e. unperceived, but primary qualities are supposed to “exist without the mind, in an unthinking substance which they call Matter.” (Part First, sect. 9)

This is a distinction that has carried forward to today. Scientists (and most of the rest of us) believe that there is no colour ‘out there’ in the world. There are only electromagnetic waves of varying lengths which our brains interpret as colour. This is analogously true for all other sensory qualities. Primary qualities, on the other hand, like extension, are held to really exist in matter, which is independent of any perceiver. Berkeley challenges this assumption, arguing that inasmuch as we deny secondary qualities external, independent reality, we ought to do the same with primary qualities.

One way Berkeley argues for this is by suggesting that primary and secondary qualities are inseparable, hence the former cannot be abstracted from the latter. There is no such thing as a real, extended body that lacks secondary qualities. Wherever we find the one, we must therefore find the other, and since it is acknowledged that secondary qualities exist only in the mind of a perceiver, that must be where we find primary qualities as well.

 

Epistemology

Berkeley identifies three objects of human knowledge, or ideas; those which come to us from our senses, those we obtain from reflecting on our mental operations and emotions, and those formed from memory and imagination.

Of these three sources of knowledge, the last two are explained/caused by the normal operation of our minds. Ideas caused by sensation, however, don’t fall into this category. They differ from these in two main ways. First, they are more vivid and constant (as in the difference between a real table and one merely remembered or imagined), and second, they are not subject to our whims (I can imagine anything I wish, whereas sensations force themselves on me). They therefore have a different source (which will turn out to be God (see the ‘Religion’ section below)). 

Finally, ideas are passive. They therefore, in contrast with conscious agents (which Berkeley calls, somewhat misleadingly to the modern ear, spirit, soul, mind, or myself) which are active and willing, cannot be the cause of anything.

 

Refutation of Scepticism

It may seem as if Berkeley’s principle leads directly into radical scepticism (which is exactly where David Hume took it). After all, he seems to be saying we ought not to inquire beyond what sensation presents us with; rather, we should just be content with these ideas and halt our investigations there. In fact, Berkeley actually thought his philosophy refutes scepticism.

Before Berkeley, it was received wisdom (a la Descartes) that Mind and Matter were separate substances. This gap was only bridgeable (i.e. knowledge was only possible) because the mind creates representations of physical matter. The scepticism lies in the fact that since we only have access to the internal representations the mind produces, we can never be certain they correlate with external reality. Berkeley overcomes this problem because he denies the existence of any external reality in the first place. Out internal ideas can’t possibly be mistaken because those internal ideas are the whole story.      

 

Ontology

One immediate consequence of Berkeley’s principle is that matter, as some corpuscular, perceiver-independent substance, doesn’t actually exist. If bodies are simply ideas in a mind, the physical, as we typically conceive of it today, isn’t real. This means that there is only one substance in existence; what Berkeley called spirit or mind, but considering his definition, “that which thinks, wills, and perceives” (Part First, sect. 138), we might better recognise as consciousness.

In addition, Berkeley thinks there are two types of ‘spirit’. The first is human, while the second is God. We will discuss God in the section on ‘Religion’ and look at human minds next.

 

Human Spirit / Mind

Berkeley doesn’t talk a lot about mind in the Treatise but he does tell us that minds are simple, undivided substances that are active in two respects. The first is in their capacity to perceive ideas. This Berkeley calls understanding. The second is the way they produce and otherwise manipulate or use ideas, and this he calls will.

Berkeley doesn’t have much to say regarding the problem of other minds in the Treatise either. All he says is that we can only be aware of the existence of other human minds through inference. Our knowledge of other people is therefore not immediate (and presumably, therefore, not certain).  

 

Cause and Effect

Matter doesn’t exist. The only things that exist are minds and the ideas those minds have. Ideas, we have seen, are passive, while minds are active. Since ideas are passive, it is impossible that one idea could affect either another idea or another mind. Yet, we see causal relations between passive objects (ideas of sensation) all the time, as in when one billiard ball strikes another causing it to move. How does Berkeley explain this?

For Berkeley, the connection we see between ideas of sensation is not a causal one; rather, the effect is a mark or sign that something has happened. One example Berkeley gives is of a noise; “the noise that I hear is not the effect of this or that motion or collision of the ambient bodies, but the sign thereof.” (Part First, sect. 65) These significations are orchestrated by God for our benefit, so that we may understand the laws of nature, which are simply the way God has arranged the universe (see the ‘Religion’ section for more on this).    

 

Religion

Bishop Berkeley was a devout Christian and much of his work was directed against ‘freethinkers’ and ‘atheists’, whom he saw as representative of the spiritual decay the England of his day was plagued by.

Given his somewhat unique metaphysics, Berkeley has an interesting argument for the existence of God. We have already seen that we don’t produce the ideas we get from sensation. Since ideas are passive, they cannot be the cause of themselves, and since matter doesn’t exist, it can’t cause them either. Where then, do ideas of sensation come from? God.

Berkeley offers three arguments against the problem of evil. First, he claims that since God created the universe in accordance with a set of “the most simple and general rules, and after a steady and consistent manner” (Part First, sect. 151), some negative outcomes were unavoidable. Second, the “blemishes and defects of nature” (Part First, sect. 152) enhance the good, by contrast. Finally, he thinks we incorrectly judge things ‘evil’. If we “enlarge our view, so as to comprehend the various ends, connections, and dependencies of things… we shall be forced to acknowledge that those particular things which, considered in themselves, appear to be evil, have the nature of good, when considered as linked with the whole system of beings.” (Part First, sect. 153)

Berkeley also argues for the immortality of the soul by recalling the distinction between bodies and spirits. The former are passive ideas in the mind, while the latter is “indivisible, incorporeal, unextended; and… consequently incorruptible.” (Part First, sect. 141)